Тёмный

Arrow's Impossibility Theorem | Infinite Series 

PBS Infinite Series
Подписаться 314 тыс.
Просмотров 170 тыс.
50% 1

Viewers like you help make PBS (Thank you 😃) . Support your local PBS Member Station here: to.pbs.org/don...
The bizarre Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem, or Arrow’s Paradox, shows a counterintuitive relationship between fair voting procedures and dictatorships. Start your free trial with Squarespace at squarespace.com... and enter offer code “infinite” to get 10% off your first purchase.
Tweet at us! @pbsinfinite
Facebook: pbsinfinite series
Email us! pbsinfiniteseries [at] gmail [dot] com
Previous Episode
Voting Systems and the Condorcet Criterion
• Voting Systems and the...
Written and Hosted by Kelsey Houston-Edwards
Produced by Rusty Ward
Graphics by Ray Lux
Made by Kornhaber Brown (www.kornhaberbrown.com)
Additional Resources
Networks, Crowds and Markets:: www.cs.cornell...
Original Paper by Kenneth Arrow:: web.archive.or...
Different voting systems can produce radically different election results, so it’s important to ensure the voting system we’re using has certain properties - that it fairly represents the opinions of the electorates. The impressively counterintuitive Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem demonstrates that this is much harder than you might think.
Thanks: Ben Houston-Edwards and Iian Smythe
Comments answered by Kelsey:
Johan Richter
• Voting Systems and the...
Nat Tuck
• Voting Systems and the...

Опубликовано:

 

10 сен 2024

Поделиться:

Ссылка:

Скачать:

Готовим ссылку...

Добавить в:

Мой плейлист
Посмотреть позже
Комментарии : 661   
@seanm7445
@seanm7445 7 лет назад
I feel these videos would be even better without colourblindness.
@eyescreamcake
@eyescreamcake 7 лет назад
The Wikipedia article on Single transferable vote uses food emojis. :D
@TalysAlankil
@TalysAlankil 7 лет назад
I assume they chose colors because they thought it would be easier/less off-puting than the usual demonstration for this theorem, which involves representing each candidate by a letter. Because that looks like algebra and a lot of people LOATHE algebra (probably without any good reason beyond "my high school math teacher sucked")
@pierrecurie
@pierrecurie 7 лет назад
She should have used simple shapes - square/circle/etc
@Melomathics
@Melomathics 7 лет назад
I like algebra, it's fun.
@rachelzimet8310
@rachelzimet8310 7 лет назад
As with voting, there are problems with any system - some people have trouble seeing the difference between such shapes.
@evanbelcher
@evanbelcher 7 лет назад
Supplementary explanation for anyone who might be feeling lost after watching: I think what they did a very bad job of is explaining where they got the ballots that they used. There was only one real set of "randomly generated" (made up) ballots. Everything else was determined from that. What they called "test cases" were not randomly generated. They were completely predetermined. They were an exhaustive list of permutations where some number of voters had purple first and the rest had purple last. The overall rankings of the test cases WERE made up. We knew that in the first test case when everyone rated purple last, purple would HAVE to be last (unanimity). Similarly, we knew that in the last test case, purple would HAVE to be first. Therefore, somewhere in the middle there, purple would have to switch from last to first. (This is of course assuming that they can't be anywhere in-between. They set this up as a homework assingment and said "figure that part out yourself" but given how essential it was to the proof, they REALLY should have explained it outright) But again, purple has to switch from last to first somewhere in the middle. In the video, we are told that the shift happens from round 2 to round 3. Again, this was made up. It could have just have easily been between any other rounds, it just would have implied a different voter as the dictator. This is what ensures that the proof is a general one. The "election results" that are presented right after this are also made up. Presumably, they were contrived to be convenient to use in the logical steps to follow. Just because it's convenient doesn't mean it's not a generalized proof, though. In this setup, voter 2 IS the dictator so any set of election results would ultimately show this conclusion. It just could be more difficult to prove with a different set of election results. From this, there's just a lot of logical inferences, all of which are difficult but valid. I had to listen to just about every sentence in the proof part of this video two times or more. The proof is all there, just not explained super clearly in my (and obviously a lot of other) opinions. Good luck!
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
I also think they should have better explained how they made the modified ballots. For each voter other than the suspect, move the polarizing candidate into the same position they are in in the two test elections for that voter (don't move any other candidate). Then pick two candidates other than the polarizing candidate. Move the polarizing candidate anywhere between them on voter2's ballot (again, don't move any other candidate). In fact I think that for the "election results" they shouldn't have given anyone except voter2 explicit rankings to make it more obvious that voter2's rankings are the only ones that matter. They do mention that they leave things out too. For example, they say you can pick _any_ two candidates. You can't. Neither can be the polarizing candidate. Proving that the polarizing candidate must be the in same place in the final rankings as in the dictator's ballot takes a little more. Some might also wonder about a method where the polarizing candidate can switch between last and first _multiple times_, though that's pretty easy to prove this cannot pass IIA and Unanimity. Suppose a method does this. Use the pair of elections around the first switch as tests, then use an election where it switches back as the "election results" of another election. You can prove that if the method really passed IIA and Unanimity, it would have to give different results (the results of the dictator).
@florencjaaarts7769
@florencjaaarts7769 4 года назад
This helped me a lot, thank you!
@IFORBIDANYDATACOLLECTIONTOALL
Exactly! Rigged just like the real thing
@realtimestatic
@realtimestatic 5 месяцев назад
bro the homework to the watcher makes no sense to me. wtf is wrong with them
@DaBTEDI
@DaBTEDI 7 лет назад
i dont understand voting with colors.. maybe you could use animals like lions... just saying
@recklessroges
@recklessroges 7 лет назад
iswydt CGPG
@columbus8myhw
@columbus8myhw 7 лет назад
("I see what you did there, C. G. P. Grey)
@twistedsim
@twistedsim 7 лет назад
We could vote for a voting system, then vote. But first, we need to vote on how to vote the voting system....
@PaulZeroSolis
@PaulZeroSolis 7 лет назад
And then we must vote the voted upon voting system in using the voted upon voting system's method of voting.
@marmorealcandors
@marmorealcandors 6 лет назад
And then we have fractals.
@DrEhrfurchtgebietend
@DrEhrfurchtgebietend 6 лет назад
This is actually the problem we are having in British Columbia right now
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
Use all voting systems to vote on the voting system. Then if they produce different winners, discuss. If there are only two winners, have a runoff.
@taylorford1689
@taylorford1689 5 лет назад
@@b43xoit But isn't that, in itself, a voting system? Who's going to vote on whetever that is good or bad?
@wrightn9
@wrightn9 7 лет назад
How did we determine that purple switched from last in round 2 to first in round 3? I know that the challenge was that it had to be either last or first, but my question is: why did the switch happen in round 3.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
The idea is that we don't know the specifics of the voting method, but we do know some of its properties, which meant we knew the winner must have switched to Purple at some point. It could have been at any point, but for an example they made it switch there.
@__-cx6lg
@__-cx6lg 7 лет назад
Nicholas Wright It didnt; that was just an exampe. She could have just as easily said the switch happened in round n, where 1
@jfb-
@jfb- 7 лет назад
It has to switch at some point, 2 was just an arbitrary example.
@memoryerror
@memoryerror 7 лет назад
But in round 3 purple is last not first?!?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
Purple was the winner of round three. 7:14
@pierreabbat6157
@pierreabbat6157 7 лет назад
Let's say that the three candidates are red, green, and blue, and that green is the polarizing candidate. Suppose that, in some election, the outcome is R>G>B. By IIA, you can run the election on just red and green, and green loses. And you can run it on green and blue, with the same voters preferring green as before, and green wins. By unanimity, there are at least one voter who prefers red to blue, at least one voter who prefers green to blue (and also to red, since green is polarizing), and at least one voter who prefers red (and blue) to green. Switch the preferences of all voters who prefer red to blue so that they prefer blue to red, without affecting whether they rank green first or last. By unanimity, blue is now above red. But by IIA, red is still above green and green is still above blue. R>G>B>R>G>.... Contradiction.
@eclipz905
@eclipz905 7 лет назад
If you plan on further discussing desirable voting system qualities, please consider Bayesian Regret. It doesn't get much attention, but you could make a strong argument that regret is more important than any collection of the standard criteria.
@antistone349
@antistone349 7 лет назад
Isn't regret minimized in a dictatorship? (Guarantees no one would have voted differently due to knowing others' votes.) That would seem to argue it is not BY ITSELF "more important than any collection of the standard criteria."
@eclipz905
@eclipz905 7 лет назад
Antistone I should have been more clear what I was meant. rangevoting.org/BayRegDum.html Bayesian Regret is a measurement of the dissatisfaction generated by a given voting system. This value is determined experimentally, using simulated elections. Each voter is assigned a satisfaction score (0-99) for each candidate. For each candidate, summing their satisfaction scores across all voters can provide a utility score. Voters then vote according to their preference (simulations can include honest voters, strategic voters, or any mix of the two). The election results are then tallied to produce a winner. The regret score for the election is determined by taking the difference between the highest utility score, and the utility score of the candidate that was actually elected. This process is performed millions of times with varying input data to determine the range of scores for each voting system. To answer your question: no, a dictatorship system does not result in low regret, because there is nothing stopping the dictator from electing a candidate with a very low utility score.
@contingenceBoston
@contingenceBoston 7 лет назад
In my unimportant opinion, the example ballots might be easier to follow if each color was accompanied by its own shape.
@DrEhrfurchtgebietend
@DrEhrfurchtgebietend 6 лет назад
Colour blind guy agrees
@florencebacus6012
@florencebacus6012 7 лет назад
Proof that a polarizing candidate must be ranked first or last: Suppose A is a polarizing candidate who is not ranked first, so that candidate B is ranked ahead of A. Let C be a third candidate. Our goal is to show that C is ranked ahead of A for any ballot. Consider a ballot which I will call Ballot 1. Since A is polarizing, for any given voter, this voter either prefers A over B and C (in the case that A is first), or she prefers B and C over A (if A is last). Equivalently, for every voter, A > C iff A > B, and A
@WoodenHorst
@WoodenHorst 3 года назад
An easier argument that proofs it: You just need IIA, unanimity is not necessary. Let's say we have candidates A,B,C. If candidate A is polarising, that means comparing only B and A will look exactly the same as comparing C and A due to IIA. Wherever B is higher than A, C must also be higher than A and vice versa, because A is either first or last. That means in the overall ranking, either B and C are higher than A or both are lower. Since this holds for any number of candidates, A is either first or last.
@nomanmcshmoo8640
@nomanmcshmoo8640 7 лет назад
What I absolutely LOVE about Infinite Series is the incredibly esoteric topics that come up as compared to many of the pop-sci channels. I.S. is definitely one of PBS' best short format video series.
@earthbjornnahkaimurrao9542
@earthbjornnahkaimurrao9542 7 лет назад
4:30 - wow plot twist. I was under the impression that Arrow's Impossibility Theorem applied to all voting systems. I am happy to learn that it doesn't and that the Cardinal Voting System may be superior to ranked voting systems.
@Sui_Generis0
@Sui_Generis0 5 лет назад
Yeah read some sen(1970) but interpersonal comparison is debated
@ivarangquist9184
@ivarangquist9184 4 года назад
The problem with Cardinal Voting is that most of the time, you don't vote according to your opinion. You are being encouraged to polarize your ratings to the maximum, which basically makes it into a binary voting system (in lack of a better name)
@Xx_BoogieBomber_xX
@Xx_BoogieBomber_xX 3 года назад
@@ivarangquist9184 That's why Arrows said that he supports a cardinal voting system where people can only vote on a scale from 1 to 3 or 1 to 4
@ccederlo
@ccederlo 13 дней назад
​@@ivarangquist9184 thankfully, STAR Voting was invented in 2014 to mitigate that problem among others!
@ahmedshaharyarejaz9886
@ahmedshaharyarejaz9886 6 месяцев назад
PBS doesn't get enough Thanks for their free content.
@lawrencetchen
@lawrencetchen 7 лет назад
Orange was definitely the polarizing color.
@corcorandm
@corcorandm 7 лет назад
So, for 1 Million dollars you'd get punched in the face? We all have our limits. I think my get punched in the face is more like -100,000
@arthurbernardocoopi6540
@arthurbernardocoopi6540 7 лет назад
corcorandm The scale is not linear, i don't think you'd be happier winning 10million dollars for no reason than winning 5million dollars than, say winning 4million dollars over losing 1million, for no reason.
@kandrc
@kandrc 7 лет назад
The scale changes with circumstances. When I was an undergraduate, I'd have taken $10 for it. As a graduate student with a nice fellowship, it would have been closer to $150. And today, with a high-paying career and a wife monitoring the bank account, I'd do it for $5.
@Noah-fn5jq
@Noah-fn5jq 7 лет назад
anything is legal if no charges are pressed. Personally I like to see it as would i rather pay someone 25$ or get punched in the face. By those standards punched in the face = -350.
@Noah-fn5jq
@Noah-fn5jq 7 лет назад
Yep. Many people would do that. Just call it a "social experiment" and you might get to get a tax break since it is work related... although that might make you susceptible to worker abuse lawsuits.
@ceramicsky14
@ceramicsky14 7 лет назад
That was a lot to take in. Definitely going to rewatch like five more times!
@pbsinfiniteseries
@pbsinfiniteseries 7 лет назад
Agreed! There's a lot of steps, but luckily, they're individually pretty manageable. I also recommend checking out the book linked to in the description. It's the main resource I used for the proof.
@TimJSwan
@TimJSwan Год назад
If 15% if people vote for chocolate, 45% for vanilla and 55% for strawberry, you might think strawberry wins and chocolate loses. That's not the case. It's because plurality voting doesn't take into account enough information. The people who wanted vanilla might have had chocolate last time but greatly prefer it to strawberry and the same could be true for the people who wanted strawberry first. So, chocolate could beat out vanilla 55% to 45% and strawberry 60% to 40% with those same voters.
@omarasad7439
@omarasad7439 Год назад
Please bring this channel back
@DrEhrfurchtgebietend
@DrEhrfurchtgebietend 6 лет назад
This is why ordinal (rank) voting is dumb. Cardinal systems are superior in every way
@Airhornsman
@Airhornsman 7 лет назад
I think there's a mistake in the voting diagram at 6:30 - between rounds 4 & 5 voter 2 changes the order of R > G > B to G > B > R
@DerToasti
@DerToasti 6 лет назад
please cover cardinal voting systems!
@XepheroiX
@XepheroiX 7 лет назад
can you do a video on cardinal voting
@michaelsommers2356
@michaelsommers2356 7 лет назад
You'll have to wait until they elect a new pope.
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
@@treyforest1999, cardinal voting will defeat the two-party scam.
@pivotman64
@pivotman64 7 лет назад
What would happen if candidates were allowed to have the same ranking?
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
Vast improvement.
@alobko1
@alobko1 7 лет назад
"You can focus on the important things like how to pack spheres in a 9 dimensional space" best Squarespace plug *ever*.
@pierrecurie
@pierrecurie 7 лет назад
I can break this theorem - everybody ties! (and is a winner and loser at the same time) 1) no dictator - nobody's opinion matters 2) IIA - no candidate matters 3) unanimity - if A is ranked higher than B by everyone, B cannot be ranked higher than A in the end
@SmileyMPV
@SmileyMPV 7 лет назад
It's worth noting that the theorem needs there to be more than two parties. If there are only two parties, say brexit or no brexit, then a democracy does work.
@KohuGaly
@KohuGaly 7 лет назад
No it doesn't solve anything, because then you have to vote on what level of brexit you want as a sequence of yes/no votes. You just arranged the voting into binomial tree in semi-arbitrary way. It's nearly identical to instant runoff.
@Desperis00
@Desperis00 7 лет назад
Here's a proof by induction on the number of candidates : First step : Two candidates, each is a polarizing candidate and each will be ranked first or last. General step : Suppose A is a polarizing candidate amongst n. By independance of irrelevant alternatives, we can remove one candidate, say B, without interfering with the overall ranking of the n-1 other candidates. By induction hypothesis, A is first or last in the result of the n-1 candidates voting. Now where does B stand in the actual voting ? the only problematic cases are when B is first and A second or when be is last and A second to last. Let's consider the first case (the second is identical) and let's change the ballots as follows. In every ballot , we move B to the least possible preffered option, without changing its position relative to A. Example : xxBxxA becomes xxxxBA and AxBxxx- becomes AxxxxB. Observe that nowany candidate but A is preffered to B by everyone but that the A vs B choice of anyone has been preserved. This is only possible because A is a polarizing candidate. According to the unanimity principle, B should now be ranked lower than any candidate but should still be ranked higher than A which is a contradiction. We discarded the two problematic cases and hence, A is ranked either first or last in the election.
@Desperis00
@Desperis00 7 лет назад
Okay, much easier but probably wrong : Suppose A is polarizing. Observe that all the ballots of A vs another candidate are identical and hence produce the same result. By the independance of irrelevant alternatives axiom, this result should be reflected in the election result. Hence A either beats anyone and is first or is beaten by anyone and is last. Now my trouble is that I don't seem to have used the unanimity axiom. And that's because I did not ! I instead used that the voting should be fair in the sense that applying a permutation to the candidates in the ballots applies the same permutation to the result. But that's not required in the original question Question : Does this fairness derives from unanimity or from unanimity+ IIA ?
@trulyUnAssuming
@trulyUnAssuming 7 лет назад
Let me adapt that a bit because I think the proof by contradiction is unnecessarily confusing in my opinion. But I like the proof. Here's a proof by induction on the number of candidates : First step : Two candidates, each is a polarizing candidate and each will be ranked first or last. General step : Suppose A is a polarizing candidate amongst n. By independence of irrelevant alternatives, we can remove one candidate, say B, without interfering with the overall ranking of the n-1 other candidates. By induction hypothesis, A is first or last in the result of the n-1 candidates voting. Case 1: B > A in the overall voting. Change the ballot as follows: In every ballot , we move B to the least preferred option, without changing its position relative to A. As A is a polarizing candidate it has to be either first which means that B is after A and can be moved to the last spot. Or A is last which means that B can be moved to the second last spot. Observe that now any candidate but A is preferred to B by everyone but that the A vs B choice of anyone has been preserved. According to the unanimity principle, B should now be ranked lower than any candidate but should still be ranked higher than A which means that A has to be ranked last. Case 2 A > B in the overall voting. Similar: Shift B up without jumping over A. Results in A ranked first.
@DaviddeKloet
@DaviddeKloet 7 лет назад
Desperis, I wrote the proof that your "fairness" derives from unanimity on another thread: ru-vid.com/video/%D0%B2%D0%B8%D0%B4%D0%B5%D0%BE-AhVR7gFMKNg.html&lc=z13lyxtxmom1tv51y23tzluompyzg5xkw.1498299129602777
@JM-us3fr
@JM-us3fr 7 лет назад
Your argument does not result in a contradiction if there is only 2 candidates since B does not need to be ranked lower than A. Obviously you already proved the case for n=2, so since you're doing it by induction it can be assumed that n>2, but you should probably mention this to make it more clear.
@trulyUnAssuming
@trulyUnAssuming 7 лет назад
+QED that is why I wanted to rewrite it. Because it wasn't quite correct but very easy to see that you can fix it.
@SmileyMPV
@SmileyMPV 7 лет назад
Proof of challenge problem: Let A be a polarizing candidate and assume it is not ranked first or last. So there exist B,C such that B>A>C. We can swap B and C whenever B>C and get a new input. By unanimity, the new output has C>B. But by irrelevance of independent alternatives, the new output has B>A>C. This contradict the transitivity property of ordering. Therefore polarizing candidates must always be ranked first or last.
@cantorscat6185
@cantorscat6185 7 лет назад
I proved the challenge problem using slightly different assumptions. Instead my assumptions are "independence of irrelevant solutions", and another property, which is that the ranking of a candidate may only be determined by the order of the votes, and not by which candidate the candidate is. We will assume candidate A is polarizing. If we only look at candidate A and candidate B, by independence of irrelevant solutions this should be enough to determine the ranking of A relative to B in the overall vote. A must be ranked < B, or > B. Example System (only looking at A and B): A B A B A B B A If we now add in the votes for one other candidate, who we will call candidate C, we will get something like this: Example System (only looking at A, B, and C): A C B A B C A C B C B A If we now only compare A and C (to determine the ranking between A and C) we get this: A C A C A C C A As you can see, this looks exactly like when we compared A and B. This is because A is a polarizing candidate, which means if any voter votes A > B for some candidate B. They must also have ranked A > every other candidate. Similarly if they ranked B < A for some candidate B, they must also have ranked every other candidate as < A. Because of the second assumption I made, C must be ranked the same way relative to A, as B was relative to A. This implies A must be ranked relative to B, the same way that A is ranked relative to any other voter. This means that if A > B, A must be > all other candidates in the overall vote, and will thus be placed first. Similarly if B > A, all other candidates must be > A, so A must be placed last in the vote. This means A is either > all other votes and first, or all other votes are > A and A is placed last. Interestingly enough, it also means that to determine if a polarizing candidate is placed first or last overall, you only need to compare that candidate to one other candidate.
@TheRealTNorty
@TheRealTNorty 7 лет назад
This is a very nice proof. I think your assumption is right: the name of the candidate is irrelevant. I used a similar assumption when I wrote my proof. Your proof is much clearer than mine though. Good job.
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
I do not think the assumption is right. As far as I know, there is no (axiomatic) reason why the voting system would treat all candidates equally, in the same way a voting system does not axiomatically have to treat all voters equally (hence the reason for having a `non-dictorial' axiom).
@billyrobertson3170
@billyrobertson3170 7 лет назад
Yeah a lot of people (including myself) seem to be making this assumption, so it's pretty natural to make I guess. I wonder if maybe there's a way to prove our assumption based on the axioms we've got... (Probably not though)
@cantorscat6185
@cantorscat6185 7 лет назад
I expect that there is a proof for when you assume "independence of irrelevant solutions" and "unanimity", but not the second assumption which I made (because I didn't use unanimity in my proof). I haven't had time to look into trying to prove it this way though, since I'm actually meant to be studying for my exams which start in half a week.
@DaviddeKloet
@DaviddeKloet 7 лет назад
I can prove your extra assumption using unanimity. Let's start by assuming your assumption is not correct. In that case there must be candidates A and B that in the same position would have different outcomes. This means that there is a candidate C and a vote V (between A and C, not including B) such that A wins against C but if you replace A with B, B loses against C. Now in V, add B next to A where on every ballot, B is right above A. Because of unanimity, B must win against A in this new vote V'. Because A wins against C, B also wins against C in V'. But because of "independence of irrelevant solutions", if you now remove A from V', B must still win against C. But this contradicts our assumption that B would lose against C in the same position.
@sabriath
@sabriath 7 лет назад
I wrote a method last time, but here's another one I've come up with: 1. choose 2 candidates, grade all ballots based on which candidate is greater. 2. Give 1 point to all ballots that correlate with the determination of which candidate is greater. 3. Repeat for all possible combinations 4. The ballot with the greatest points is the "dictator," their score is the only one that matters. ?
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
Not sure I understand. But it appears to use ranking ballots, so must be subject to Arrow.
@michaeldavies6159
@michaeldavies6159 7 лет назад
Challenge problem solution: Let P be a polarising candidate and suppose P is neither first nor last in the result. So there must be candidates A and B such that A > P > B in the result. Consider all possible relative positions of A, B, P a ballot might have: 1) P > A > B 2) P > B > A 3) A > B > P 4) B > A > P Take all the ballots with A > B (i.e. 1s and 3s) and swap A and B (so there are only 2s and 4s left over). None of the A > P and P > B rankings were removed so by IIA final result still has A > P and P > B, and hence A > B. But by unanimity the final result must have B > A, contradiction.
@DaviddeKloet
@DaviddeKloet 7 лет назад
Challenge problem: Proof by contradiction: Let's assume we have a voting V where A is a polarizing candidate but neither first nor last in the final result. We'll derive a contradiction from this. Because A is not first, there is candidate B winning against A. Because A is not last there is a candidate C losing against A. Now add a candidate X to V just above B on every ballot. Because of unanimity, X must win against B and therefore against A. Now remove all candidates other than X and A and call the results V1. Because of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, X also beats A in V1. Now, instead, add X to V just below C on every ballot. Because of unanimity, X must lose from C and therefore from A. Now remove all candidates other than X and A and call the results V2. Because of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, X also loses from A in V2. Because A is polarizing, on every ballot its position relative to every other candidate is the same and so V1 and V2 must be identical. So X can't lose from A in V1 and win against A in V2. And there is our contradiction. QED
@joangalt6270
@joangalt6270 2 года назад
But your "Candidate A" MUST be either first or last according to the theorem (and this is the only part that made sense to me). And it DOES make sense. Substitute Trump as the polarizing candidate. Trump PROVED the theorem because he WAS first (supported by his base, Conservatives, Red States) or he WAS last, NOT the preferred candidate for liberal voters, Blue States, etc. This is how we have this shitty man in the WH now - Trump was polarizing. But more people were against him than for him (allegedly) thus, he came in LAST. So your outlier situation cannot happen. The ONLY situation the scenario MIGHT have issues of validity is if TWO polarizing candidates run for office. What then? But, even in this case, one would still be first or last bc they can't BOTH be first AND last simultaneously! WHEW! IDK if that even makes any sense. When substituting Trump as the polarizing candidate, the theorem IS ALWAYS TRUE.
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
Challenge question: Let P be a polarising candidate. Suppose for contradiction that P is not in first and not in last. This means there are candidates A and B such that the group ranks A above P and P above B. Now imagine changing all the votes as follows: --If a voter preferred B over A, leave their vote unchanged. --If a voter preferred A over B, swap around the positions of A and B in their vote, leaving all their other preferences unchanged. Now observe that the voting system will continue to rank A above P: Changing individual preferences between A and B does not change individual preferences between A and P (because P is polarising), and so by Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, A is still ranked above P. Similarly, the voting system will continue to rank P above B. Hence, A is ranked above B. But every voter prefers candidate B over candidate A, contradicting Unanimity.
@th_rtyf_re
@th_rtyf_re 7 лет назад
For the challenge lemma, the independence of irrelevant alternatives is all we need: For each candidate (named A) other than the polarizing candidate (named P), we can construct a corresponding sequence of 1's and 0's such that if the kth voter ranked A above P, the kth digit is a 1, and otherwise it's a 0. For example in the round 2 of the example (around 7:00), green is given the sequence 01111, with purple being the polarizing candidate. We find that blue and red also given this sequence: in fact, the sequences corresponding to *all* candidates other than P are the same because P is polarizing (and so the other candidates are always grouped together on one side or another of P). The independence of irrelevant alternatives implies that the relative ranking of A and P in the global ranking is only a function of their relative rankings on the individual ballots; that is, it's a function of A's corresponding binary sequence. Therefore, since all the sequences are the same, P's ranking relative to any other candidate (in the global ranking) is the same: thus P is either ranked first or last. ◼︎ I didn't use unanimity in this proof because the lemma actually holds for any voting system and its opposite, the "opposite" being the voting system that returns the opposite ranking that the original voting system would give. If one of these systems verifies the unanimity property, the other one doesn't, but they both put polarizing candidates first or last.
@halulife35
@halulife35 7 лет назад
im having some trouble understanding how purple is ranked first overall in round 3. i get that purple is polarizing, but in round 3 it's still ranked last 3 out of 5 times, which just doesn't appear sufficient enough to warrant first overall to me. round 4 is legit, i can totally see that. it just makes no sense lol at 11:00, the election results, green was ranked higher than blue 4 out of 5 times. i 100% fail to see how that means blue is greater than green. that makes no sense to me.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
They were supposing that the "mystery system" said Purple was the winner of round 3. They could have changed that supposition so that Purple didn't become the winner until round 4, and then voter 3 would have to be the dictator. That's the key here; the only things we know about the "mystery method" is that is passes Unanimity, IIA, and gives some specific results in test elections. Everything else necessarily follows from that. Think of it this way: The reason why it looks so weird is probably because you were assuming that the method is at least _trying_ to be "fair". But the whole point of this video is to show that this method _absolutely is not even trying to be fair, it's dictatorial through and through_ . It passes both Unanimity and IIA, so someone must be the dictator from the beginning and their ballot is the only one that matters, no matter what anyone else puts down.
@fred315h
@fred315h 7 лет назад
I know right... I really want to understand it, but that part just bugs me.
@MrRoyalChicken
@MrRoyalChicken 7 лет назад
You don't know the voting system used in this election. the point is that in one of the states between everyone choosing purple last and everyone choosing purple first the election tips in purples favour. It's only an example that this happens in round three. It could have happened in round four or five but the following logic to show that that person is the dictator still stands. Concerning the ranking at 11:00, I'm pretty sure it's a mistake.
@fred315h
@fred315h 7 лет назад
+Skyval_Ream That is a cyclical argument. If we are trying to show that an voting system is unfair, we can't start with it being unfair. Likewise, for their argument to be sound, they can't just make the results unfair and then say that it is so... I also don't care which voting round the change happened in. Their modified results have Green beting Purple, just like in vote round 3, yet they state the opposite. Regardless of which voter is "suppose" to become the dictator, the method of finding said dictator MUST be fair. Else you are creating false positives. Don't get me wrong, I want to understand this, but i can't.
@johanrichter2695
@johanrichter2695 7 лет назад
Another election-related topic of mathematical interest is apportionment/proportional representation. The methods discussed/used in the US for distributing seats in the House of Representatives among the states are often the same as those used in Europe to distribute seats among parties in party list-PR systems. There are some nice and surprising algorithms to do that, and some surprising paradoxes involing intuitively appealing methods. I suggest a video on that.
@AmosOfSynhome
@AmosOfSynhome 7 лет назад
In your last video you stated that the pairwise comparison system that led to the Condorcet Paradox failed. But I would argue that it didn't. It revealed that there was no group preference.
@alexwang982
@alexwang982 7 лет назад
On the Condorcet thumbnail the cycle is a mobius loop
@johanrichter2695
@johanrichter2695 7 лет назад
It is perhaps worth noting one reason that Arrow focused on ranked voting systems was philosophical. He thought that we can't compare the intensity of preference between different people so the maximal information we can have is everone's list of preferences.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
But later in his life he changed his mind and said Score with "three or four classes" was probably best.
@catStone92
@catStone92 7 лет назад
so we're doing cardinal voting next, right? this video made too much of a buildup for you guys to do otherwise :P
@williamdaly422
@williamdaly422 7 лет назад
Yay! so glad you finally did one on Arrow's impossibility theorem! please do more on social choice theory and fair division
@Nothing_serious
@Nothing_serious 7 лет назад
William Daly I think they already did fair division.
@williamdaly422
@williamdaly422 7 лет назад
Your Waifu Sucks ahhh yes! I can't believe I missed the rent division one, thanks for pointing that out!
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
Maybe in the future they'll do Cake Cutting algorithms!
@florencjaaarts7769
@florencjaaarts7769 4 года назад
I was so confused after watching this the first three times, but I rewatched it, thought about it, read more, wrote it out myself, and now it makes sense! Thank you!
@robharwood3538
@robharwood3538 7 лет назад
So glad you tackled this topic! Better voting systems could potentially solve a bazillion political problems we have right now, in the US and around the world.
@justinlandis9666
@justinlandis9666 7 лет назад
My attempt at the Challenge question, prove"If a voting system has Unanimity and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, then there must be a polarizing candidate who is ranked either first or last." We should start by assuming the voting system has both Unanimity and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives. Unanimity implies that everyone who has voted will rank one color over another color. Lets call the color of preference "Color A" and the other color "Color B." Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives implies that changing the ranking of some color C will never change the relative ranking of Color A to Color B. Use Unanimity to find the most preferred color in the voting system. Since our voting system has unanimity we may search for the most preferred color. If Color A is the most preferred color, namely no other color is ranked higher pairwise to all other colors, then we are done and we found the polarizing candidate who is ranked only first. If not, then there must exist another color everyone prefers to A. Since A is always preferred to B this new color must also be preferred to B. Repeat this process until the most preferred color is found. We may use Unanimity to find the least preferred color in the similar way. We either say B is the least preferred color or there must be another color which is ranked under B. We have thus constructed an ordered ranking of colors with Unanimity. Stating that our voting system has Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives means that the relative ranking of two colors will stay the same if the third is adjusted. This implies that our original ordered ranking could have been something like this C>.....>A>B>......>D where C was the most preferred and D was the least preferred. However we can change the ranking of A to be such that A>C>......>B>......>D Where C is still greater than all previous pairwise combinations (specifically C>B>D) Given this fact, we know that there must always be a polarizing candidate who is either ranked first or last. In this case I suppose there is two polarizing candidates, one ranked first and one ranked last. Let me know what you think.
@mohalobaidi
@mohalobaidi 7 лет назад
can anyone explain whay purple above green at 10:41 😅
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
Vote Test 3 is round 3 from earlier in the video. At the time, Kelsey supposed the mystery system said Purple was the winner in round 3, which means Purple was preferred to Green. Each of the modified ballots have the same relative rankings for Purple and Green. So, by IIA, Purple must be preferred to green with the modified ballots.
@SendyTheEndless
@SendyTheEndless 7 лет назад
Can we even democracy?
@eyescreamcake
@eyescreamcake 7 лет назад
Only if we the whole voting system.
@RobertAdoniasCostaGomes
@RobertAdoniasCostaGomes 7 лет назад
democracy isn't the same as election-based representative democracy... if we just randomly select people out of everybody, we possibly get the most accurate type of representative democracy possible...
@eyescreamcake
@eyescreamcake 7 лет назад
Only if you average it out over long periods of time. (But political opinion changes over such long periods of time, so no, random ballot is not really representative at all.) After all, the optimal strategy in a random ballot election is to write-in your own name...
@RobertAdoniasCostaGomes
@RobertAdoniasCostaGomes 7 лет назад
well, if it is random, you wouldn't have to write a ballot, right? but I do agree on the point about statistical flops... I would just argue that random selection does not work in a republic, specially one as large as the US at the federal level... but, if no one has job stability in politics, then no one is boss and everybody rules, which is basically what a democracy is... one could discuss the need for a fixed president that gets elected, though I think this should be better suited for PBS Demos channel * subtle suggestion for a political sciences/sociology channel *
@Sempoo
@Sempoo 7 лет назад
We need weighted democracy - every voter has weighted vote, i.e. college professor will have higher weight than factory worker.
@nickelmouse451
@nickelmouse451 6 лет назад
The condition which holds that - if orange drops out of the race, that should not change if green is preferred to red in the overall ranking, is not Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA). Its is Sen's condition alpha. IIA holds that - whether or not x is preferred (or indifferent) to y in our social choice ranking should not depend on where any other candidate, z, falls within the individual preference rankings. This is not the same as condition alpha, which holds that - if x is preferred to y in candidate set S, then we remove some elements of S and end up with S’, x ought to be preferred to y in S’ so long as neither was removed.
@NathanTAK
@NathanTAK 7 лет назад
I get this paranoid feeling Arrow's Impossibility Theorem corresponds directly with Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems...
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
I'm thinking, not so much.
@rohansharma1250
@rohansharma1250 7 лет назад
2 continuous videos on topics discussed by undefined behaviour!
@rafael17264
@rafael17264 6 лет назад
my brain has a lot fun while i watch this,but after some time it gets tired and makes a decision to pause for a little bit :D *that's a compliment
@isaacdarche7103
@isaacdarche7103 Год назад
The distinction between "Arrow's idealized world" and "the real world" (resp. Satterwhite et al) is spurious. Arrow shows that for 2 or more choices, social choice mechanisms cannot satisfy all necessary rationality criteria (the ideal world). If you relax the rationality criteria (the real world), rationality criteria are still not satisfied. So, the statement "Arrow's Theorem does not apply to the real world" is false.
@rkpetry
@rkpetry 7 лет назад
This series hasn't yet touched on the purpose and value of votation and systematicization (but neither did probability-and-statistics textbooks 50 years ago)-Single-objective voting itself is nearly impossible to realize, so we'll count it roguish nation (e.g. war vs. snooze)... more-realistic votation systems should probably serve up choices of decision-graphing....
@rkpetry
@rkpetry 7 лет назад
[04:13] Also, How does Independence-of-Irrelevants relate to Distinguishable-from-random-voting (which you don't mention, the entropic-zone width)...
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
?
@hughobyrne2588
@hughobyrne2588 3 года назад
"Independence of irrelevant alternatives" reminds me of the psychological pricing trick that I've heard called "spoilers". I forget the particulars, but it goes something like this: At a movie theater, they sell three sizes of drink, small, medium (about the size of 2 smalls) and large (about 3 smalls). The prices are $1.00, $1.95 and $2.15, respectively. Now, the medium seems like a terrible choice - and virtually no-one chooses it - but the very existence of the medium size at that price, makes the large look like great value. The movie theater across the street has the same small size, and the same large size, at the same prices, but they don't sell as many large drinks because the "spoiler" medium size - the "irrelevant alternative" - makes a difference. This result is shown in real psychological tests, it's something that really happens in the world.
@tommyrosendahl7238
@tommyrosendahl7238 7 лет назад
Could you do a video on Gödel's incompleteness theorems? That would be amazingly interesting...
@timbeaton5045
@timbeaton5045 7 лет назад
I suspect it MAY just take more than one video! That may also be true, but unprovable within the system.
@michaelscholes8956
@michaelscholes8956 11 дней назад
3:10 someone please explain to me how orange ranks first here? Seems to me it should be green, blue, then orange 1-3
@ForYourMath
@ForYourMath 7 лет назад
If we're going to be pedantic, then the challenge problem is wrong unless we define being ranked first and last to include ties. For example, what if we have two people voting for blue or red, and person 1 ranks blue above red, while person 2 ranks red above blue?
@ShawarmaHunter
@ShawarmaHunter 7 лет назад
this theorem is always cited as some important fact about voting, and it assumes ordinal voting. if we use cardinal voting we can solve this all kerfuffle. sure, cardinal voting doesn't guarantee a definite answer in all cases, but if our system is fair (whatever that means) and has concluded that two candidates are identically good in the eyes of the populous - than just flip a coin, who cares. they're both literally exactly as good. is there another more substantial downside to cardinal voting? or did arrow's theorem just came about because we purposelessly imposed the restriction of ordinality upon ourselves?
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
I suppose that when Arrow found the theorem, nobody was considering cardinal systems yet.
@sunriseinspector
@sunriseinspector 7 лет назад
Good job of breaking the proof into parts and preparing us for what was coming. You are very good at your explanations and the parts that you leave for us to prove are well thought out and fun to try.
@JM-us3fr
@JM-us3fr 7 лет назад
I wonder if this is why so many civilizations start out with chiefs and kings; in pursuit of perfect fairness, you unintentionally create autocracy.
@TheLoneGnu
@TheLoneGnu 7 лет назад
Challenge problem solution: Lemma: If a voting system satisfies Unanimity (U) and Independence of irrelevant Alternatives (IIA). Then a polarizing candidate must be ranked first or last. Proof: We prove this by induction. When there are 2 or less candidates any candidate will either be ranked first or last, so the induction start is trivial. Assume the lemma to hold for n-1 candidates, and consider a voting result with n>2 candidates with a polarizing candidate p. Let c be a candidate that is not p. If we remove c from the ballot it will not change the fact that p is a polarizing candidate, and since there are then n-1 candidates (in this case) we know by the induction assumption that p will come out first or last. We are going to assume here that p comes out last in the election with c removed, the proof for when p come out first is simmilar. By IIA the final order of all the candidates that are not c will be the same as the order of them when c was removed - that means all we have to prove is that c is ranked higher (ranked before) p in the final rank. If we change the current casting of the votes such that all the voters that placed p first places c second, and the rest (the ones that placed p last - since p is polarizing) places c first - all of this without changing the order of the other candidates - then c will be placed before all candidates that are not p on all the ballots, and therefore by IIA and U c will end up before all the n-2>0 candidates that are niether c nor p, but since the relative position of these n-2 candidates and p will be unchanges, they will still end up before p. That is c is ranked higher than n-2 candidates (at least 1) that are all/is ranked higher than p thereby c is ranked higher than p. Notice now that if we swap back to the orriginal voting, the relative order of c and p will not change, so since c won over p before the swap, it will again after the swap. Thereby p will end up last. As mentioned before you can make a very similar argument for when p ends up first in the voting with n-1 candidates then p will end up first in the voting with n candidates, which concludes the induction step and thus the proof! QED.
@buchweiz
@buchweiz 7 лет назад
The challenge problem is mostly about working out mathematical notation to me. So let's say that we have input vectors x_j which represents how a voter "j" ranked all candidates by giving them numbers from 1 to n (the first coordinate x_1j encodes the rank given to the first candidate, x_2j encodes the rank given to the second and so on). Now for convenience let's pack all of these vectors together into a matrix [x_ij] and run it through a function f([x_ij])=y, where y is results of the elections and the final rank of a candidate "k" is y_k=f_k([x_ij])=f(x_11,...,x_ij,...x_nN) with N being the number of voters. Now let's translate conditions of unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives into this notation. Unanimity would be: if for every voter "j" candidate "m" has a lower rank than candidate "l" i.e. x_li>x_mi for every i, it means y_l>y_m. And independence means that for the result of a candidate "k" it is irrelevant, if we swap ranks of two other candidates for a specific voter or that f_k(x_li,x_mi)=f_k(x_mi, x_li) for every l,m≠k. I'm going to assume for simplicity that the polarizing candidate is candidate "1", i.e. x_1i= 1 or n for every i. Finally the proof goes as follows: first assume that every voter chooses x_1j=n, this automatically means from the condition of unanimity that y_1=n. The opposite (x_1j=1 for every j) by the same logic gives the result y_1=1, but first let's concentrate on y_1=n. If now any random voter "j" changes his mind about candidate "1", it means he must swap him with candidate he ranked first "l", since 1 is a polarizing candidate and can be either first or last (it also shouldn't undermine the generality of taking into account all possible voter choices since l and j are chosen completely arbitrarily at this point). So in this notation x_1j=1 and x_lj=n, but because of the independence condition f_k(x_1j,x_lj)=f_k(x_lj,x_1j) for every k, or in other words the rankings of all other candidates aside from "1" and "l" should remain unchanged. After the swap it's either that the candidate "1" is still the loser with rank n or now he has swapped places with candidate "l" and is now the winner. If the candidate "1" is still loosing we can continue the process with voters changing their opinions about him until the voter is found, whose change of hearts determines the result of the election, and we know this is guaranteed to happen due to the fact that, if all of voters rank the candidate 1 first, he's going to win.
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
Two errors in your reasoning: 1) Your translation of indep or irrel alternatives is not correct. This axiom says that relative rank of two particular candidates is only dependent on individuals' preferences of those two particular candidates. I do not know how to write that in your notation. What you say is that a candidates rank is unaffected if an individual changes their preference of two other candidates, which is not the same. 2) You only considered swaps which involve the polarising candidate 1 in your argument. However, you need to also consider swaps that involve two other candidates.
@Noah-fn5jq
@Noah-fn5jq 7 лет назад
Solution for challenge question: Proof by contradiction - assume the result is A>P>B where P is a polarizing candidate. Now, if we allow A to be an irrelevant variable, then for all voters that selected P to be in first place, due to independence of irrelevant variables, we can place A in first. This will cause the placement of P to now be last (due to the rule of a polarized candidate) and that causes all voters to think that B>P. Due to unanimity, this contradicts the result. Similar argument can be used to show that P>A. Please note that this argument can be used to show that P must be in both first AND last place at the same time within the results. Thus any election with more than two candidates cannot have both unanimity and independence of irrelevant variables while using this election type (even if there is only one voter)... sigh.
@eli0damon
@eli0damon 7 лет назад
I feel like there should be some close relationship between independence of irrelevant alternatives and preclusion of strategic voting. Is there one? And if so, what is it? Thanks.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
Well according to another theorem that even applies to cardinal system, no system is immune to strategy (unless it's dictatorial, or nondeterministic, etc.) (Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem) But IIA failure can lead to strategy. Plurality's spoiler effect is an example of IIA failure, and it leads people to voting only for the front-runner they prefer, even if they still don't like them, instead of supporting someone they like more.
@aresmars2003
@aresmars2003 6 лет назад
My Plurality Criterion says "A Condorcet winner who is also the plurality winner should never lose." With that requirement, top-two runoff passes, while IRV fails. In IRV, the plurality candidate may fall to 3rd place and be eliminated and never get a chance for a head-to-head comparison to his rivals. It's important because REAL WORLD voting includes compromise before the election, and so using a voting method with this criterion encourages voters to "agree to agree" before the election, and that prevents the threat of elections like 100 candidates and 100 voters where rational ranking is impossible. If you know "I have to be first or second most popular", weaker candidates may choose to endorse someone else before the election even occurs.
@aresmars2003
@aresmars2003 6 лет назад
The 2017 Minneapolis Mayor election was interesting (with IRV or RCV): 5 strong candidates, and the plurality candidate won in the end, while the plurality-second candidate was eliminated after falling to 4th place. With a close race at 2nd,3rd,4th for elimination order, any of the top-4 candidates might have been the Condorcet candidate, but we'll never know. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Minneapolis_mayoral_election,_2017
@pedraumbass
@pedraumbass 7 лет назад
It's important to state that this only works if there are 3 or more candidates.
@Tracks777
@Tracks777 7 лет назад
Awesome video
@cabb99
@cabb99 7 лет назад
Do you think you will be able to explain cardinal voting systems too? Or do you think it is too far off topic from the series? I was always curious about what is the best option to treat the non valid votes (people who don't give a complete information about their preferences)
@TheTrueAdept
@TheTrueAdept Год назад
There are cullinaries to Arrow's Impossibility Theorem that go with other voting systems. Basically, it ends to end-state that Arrow's Theorem ended up with.
@rufatsadigov4375
@rufatsadigov4375 5 лет назад
What about the property of unrestricted domain for proving the Arrow's theorem? Or only unanimity and IIA are enough to show dictatorship?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 5 лет назад
I think they simplified some things for the video.
Год назад
The dictatorship kinda happen in majority between as well, if you have a tie. The next vote will be the "dictator".
@felooosailing957
@felooosailing957 4 года назад
There is a question that I have never really understood: does plurality voting (candidate with most votes in First round wins) count as an example of Ranked choice voting? I believe it does, but I would like to know how the properties discussed here apply for it.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 4 года назад
First, the phrase "Ranked Choice Voting" mostly came about as a "marketing" term for IRV+STV, even though there are other rank-based methods (e.g. Borda, most Condorcet methods) I would say that a method should require ranks in order to be called rank-based. A method that you could fully express using ranks, but doesn't doesn't require it, I wouldn't call rank-based. Although you could do a Plurality election using ranked ballots, it'd be unnecessary and redundant, so I wouldn't consider it rank-based Then again, being able to use ranked ballots is what matters for this theorem, so it does apply to plurality, if that's what you're asking
@JohnLangleyAkaDigeratus
@JohnLangleyAkaDigeratus 2 месяца назад
Thank you SO MUCH, this is an excellent video!
@AmosOfSynhome
@AmosOfSynhome 7 лет назад
Note that the pairwise comparisons system described at the start of the first video meets both unanimity and a weaker (but still pretty strong) version of Independence from irrelevant alternatives. Adding a candidate never reverses a group preference but can only turn a clear group preference into a paradox. So A>B can't be changed to B>A by the introduction of option C. Instead it can only be turned into an ABC cycle or paradox. If you, as I do, consider a paradox to be a tie then adding a candidate can turn A>B into A=B. The worst effect of the way other systems turn A>B into B>A by the introduction of C is how that leads to tactical voting which denies the system true data to analyze.
@vibhuvikramaditya4576
@vibhuvikramaditya4576 6 месяцев назад
You are wrong on one crucial point, The arrow impossibility theorem doesn't just apply to Ranked choice ordinal voting, Borda system which provides cardinal numbers based on ordinal collective preferences doesn't satisfy the independence from irrelevant alternatives, as the number of options and rank has direct implications for votes. The theorem is general in nature and applies to all voting systems
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 6 месяцев назад
Borda is still generally considered a ranked method, whether the ranks are technically used to assign points isn't really relevant to the theorem (they even talk about it in their previous video) A better example would be Score voting, which can't losslessly be encoded using ranks. Then whether it passes IIA or not depends on how you define it for rating-based systems. Generally, if you extend the concept of IIA in a way that preserves its spirit, Score passes it (and all the others) without becoming a dictatorship. But there are other ways to extend it where Score fails (and I think Arrow's theorem still technically applies), but then it's blatantly obvious that it's not desirable when defined that way.
@ImaginaryMdA
@ImaginaryMdA 7 лет назад
Suppose we have pink be a polarizing color, (as it tends to be). Then for every other color we choose, getting rid of irrelevant alternatives produces the same 2 color election. If for voter A, pink was last, then no matter what color we compare it to, that other color will be always be ranked higher, and so on for every other voter. So if the election decides that pink is ranked higher than any given other color, it must rank pink higher than all other colors, due to the rule of irrelevant alternatives. Hence pink is first, if it wins any 2 color election, and last otherwise.
@TimJSwan
@TimJSwan Год назад
Dictator and ties don't matter. Neither does it matter if there is a circular condorcet mapping. What matters is that plurality is an extremely poor voting method because in a real situation with hundreds of candidates and millions of voters, a condorcet vote could have opposite results than plurality. It doesn't matter if there's a tie because it's not a lie, whereas a plurality vote gives results based on the candidate space. That's why they tried to hack the math by adding parties.
@7lllll
@7lllll 7 лет назад
the arrow's theorem i know of splits unanimity into two parts. One part requires that there exists a set of votes that outputs any given outcome, and the other part requires that when one candidate's rank is increased by some voters and decreased by none, then that candidate's rank cannot fall. it feels like unanimity is simpler, but is there some mathematical advantage of stating it in this way instead?
@humbertoseghetto5218
@humbertoseghetto5218 7 лет назад
What about a "reverse" borda count? every candidate wins as many points as his rank (first candidare gets 1 point, second gets 2...) and the winner is the one with least points?
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
Same outcome as Borda count, just using golf scores.
@AmosOfSynhome
@AmosOfSynhome 7 лет назад
The pairwise system includes only one opportunity for tactical voting and that would be an attempt to create a paradox or cycle that includes your preferred candidate. But you would only be interested in doing so if your first choice candidate were likely to come second. But engineering a paradox with a single vote is very difficult because you can't vote for the entire paradox but only two sides of the cycle (engineering a more than three sided cycle would be even harder so I am assuming three sides). The third side of the cycle you have to vote against. So you would have to determine from polling results which side of the cycle is most easily turned and make certain your vote reinforces the cyclw on that side. But too many people tactically vote and they will turn another side undoing the cycle and potentially helping their least preferred candidate to win. Thus the system deters what little tactical voting is possible under it by making it very likely to backfire.
@unvergebeneid
@unvergebeneid 7 лет назад
Maybe it should be noted why independence of irrelevant alternatives matters: it's another way of saying that every voter should be able to express their true preference, without any strategic voting according to how they expect others to vote.
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
No voting system eliminates the benefit of strategy, per the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem.
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
But with Approval Voting, your best strategy is never to betray your favorite nor to elevate your most hated. And when two voters have opposite positions on all the candidates, their votes cancel. So that is some evidence that the system may be giving every vote equal power, thus removing any incentive to choose power over merit.
@theultimatereductionist7592
@theultimatereductionist7592 6 лет назад
We proved Arrow's Theorem in graduate math class in 1992 at Rutgers University. I find nothing special or important about one of those axioms. The one that forbids candidate X from being group-ranked 1st place in spite of no voter ranking X 1st place. I see no particular reason why one "needs" or "should have" that assumption. As long as everybody agrees on the particular algorithm to generate a group ranking from individual voter rankings, there's no logical reason to rule out X being group ranked highest.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 6 лет назад
Does that axiom have a name? I don't think it's part of Arrow's theorem, or at least it isn't necessary. It isn't in this video's proof, for example. There are rank-based methods where the winner isn't necessarily put first by anyone, most notably Condorcet methods, but that's not the reason they fail Arrow's theorem---it's because they fail IIA, which I'm pretty sure is different.
@GoldenKingStudio
@GoldenKingStudio 7 лет назад
Some interpretations argue that using cardinal methods do not actually avoid Arrow's Impossibility Theorem because cardinal information from one person is not directly comparable to the information obtained from another person. Plus, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem still applies, as well as various extensions and related theorems. This means that gaming the system will always be possible, making some people want to vote against their own actual preferences in order to obtain a more desirable result (which also applies to Ordinal Systems). Thus, a Cardinal System is not necessarily an obvious choice against an Ordinal System. Unless you only have one voter and/or one candidate, there will always be some way the system is flawed. Even a system as simple when there are two parties, there can be the chance of a tie if there are an even number of voters. Plus, not everyone in a population does vote, and so questions have to be raised as to what counts as a win. If only one person out of an arbitrarily large voting population decides to vote, then that person alone decides the election, against the wishes of who knows how many people.
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
I'm not sure I can prove this or express it clearly, but I think that the answer to the objection about incomparability of cardinal information from one person to another is just to demand that the system accord each person the same amount of power over the outcome as every other person. This can be fairly reasonably tested for by asking whether for every possible vote in the system, its exact opposite would also be permitted. For example, if I support Stein and Bush and oppose Gore, and you support Gore and oppose Stein and Bush, then in Approval Voting your and my votes cancel, so we both have the same amount of power. If our votes don't cancel or one of us can't express it within the rules of the system, but the other can, then the system is giving one of us more power than it is giving the other.
@BrunoJMR
@BrunoJMR 7 лет назад
What makes voter 2 specifically the dictator? What are the conditions of the distribution for a specific voter to be the dictator? And is there any way to manipulate your way into dictatorship?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
It was because we supposed the "mysterious" method switched Purple to be 1st between 2 and 3; that's when voter 2 switched. In this case, if the "mystery" method also meets Unanimity and IIA, then the only method it could possibly be is one that considers voter 2 to be the dictator. They could have made it switch between other rounds. In which case a different voter would be responsible. That would be a "different" method but it would still be dictatorial. As long as you use the exact same method, that "same" voter will always be the dictator; whatever is on their ballot will be the final rankings, no matter what the other ballots say.
@RaindropsBleeding
@RaindropsBleeding 4 года назад
wouldn't a mean value ranking system satisfy most of these? Sort of the inverse of a point system. any time a color is ranked 1st it recieves 1 point, 2nd place is 2 points, etc, and the total is averaged, so the mean value comes very close to the rank that color recieves most often. the colors are then ranked by this new mean value. in the case of a tie, a second round of just those two colors is calculated. this satisfies unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives. it's also not dictatorial. using this system the switch for purple occurs evenly across all rounds, as it should, and does not affect the rankings of any of the other colors, other than bumping one to achieve its rank
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 4 года назад
Isn't this equivalent to Borda? It prefers smaller scores, but gives smaller scores to higher ranked candidates. Using means shouldn't change the final ranking. And Borda fails IIA. Using a common "Capital of Tennessee" election example between (M)emphis, (N)ashville, (C)hattanooga, and (K)noxville: 42x M>N>C>K 26x N>C>K>M 15x C>K>N>M 17x K>C>N>M Means: Memphis: 2.74 Nashville: 2.06 Chattanooga: 2.27 Knoxville: 2.93 Nashville wins But if voters who preffer Chattanooga to Nashville use strategic burial: 42x M>N>C>K 26x N>C>K>M 15x C>K>M>N 17x K>C>M>N Means: Memphis: 2.42 Nashville: 2.38 Chattanooga: 2.27 Knoxville: 2.93 The C vs N orders did not change on any ballots, but the winner changed from N to C (hopefully I did the math correctly)
@RaindropsBleeding
@RaindropsBleeding 4 года назад
@@MustSeto I hadn't considered strategic burial. Also, yes, this is effectively an inverted form of Borda that achieves roughly the same results. I may have to crunch the numbers to see if it ever differs, but it also fails the Condorcet Criterion so... perhaps a better method could be used.
@brunosanchez1375
@brunosanchez1375 7 лет назад
I´m confused, does election in america work by ranking the candidates? in my country works by choosing only one preference for a candidate and counting the total votes. Does this still works then?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
This applies to choose-one plurality. Plurality is like a ranked system where everyone but whoever is ranked first is ignored. So in practice there's zero reason to actually rank them.
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
Unfortunately, almost all elections in the US operate the same way as in your country. The people must defeat this system.
@edelopo
@edelopo 7 лет назад
I have a question regarding what you mean by voting system. I would assume that in a voting system all voters are indistinguishable, meaning that if we permute the votes, the outcome would be the same. Therefore if all voters cast different votes and there is a dictator, permuting the votes may result in the dictator making a different vote, but the outcome should remain the same. How does this exactly work?
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
So in the definition of a voting system, I think we do not assume that voters are indistinguishable. Nor do we assume that the candidates are indistinguishable. In principle, it would be nice to have the permuting property you describe. However, no such voting system can exist, because you can have completely symmetric votes: 1. A>B>C 2. B>C>A 3. C>A>B
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
@@TheManxLoiner, in all seriously proposed voting systems, permuting the ballots has no effect on the outcome.
@prithwishguha309
@prithwishguha309 3 года назад
I don't understand, why did you said overall it's purple above green in modified bollots and vote test 3; when it's actually green above purple
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 3 года назад
If the method was majoritarian, then yes green would be above purple. But we didn't assume majoritarianism, only Unanimity and IIA.
@WatchCuriousCat
@WatchCuriousCat 7 лет назад
[Cries in colorblindness]
@nasmith99dominion10
@nasmith99dominion10 7 лет назад
Is there any way you could avoid using blue and purple together in future videos? I'm colorblind and I couldn't distinguish between them.
@MackJCM
@MackJCM 7 лет назад
The weekly problem is trivial given Arrow's Impossibility Theorem. If there is only one ballot, then the only polarizing candidates are ranked first and last respectively by this singular ballot. These candidates rank first and last in the dictatorial vote, respectively. If there is more than one ballot, then by Arrow's Impossibility Theorem, our assumptions are violated. Therefore in every case that we have those two properties, every polarizing candidate must rank first or last. QED.
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
In the video, we use this challenge problem to prove Arrow's Impossibility Theorem, so it would be cyclic reasoning to prove the problem using the Theorem. You need to answer the problem only using the two properties given.
@MackJCM
@MackJCM 7 лет назад
Okay, I've got it now: If there are one or two candidates the property holds trivially. Suppose there are at least three candidates A, B, and C, such that B is a polarizing candidate in the election, and our system's relative ranking order is A>B>C (that is, B is polarizing but not first or last). Every voter either ranks both A and C above B, or both of them below B. Now suppose that for this same system and election, the results are changed such that every voter who ranked A above C swaps the positions of those two candidates on their ballots. Then every voter will have ranked C above A. It follows from unanimity that C must beat A in the overall ranking. However, it follows from independence of irrelevant alternatives that B must continue to beat C, since the relative positions of B and C never changed on any ballot. As well, A must beat B. So we have that A>B>C must hold, and C>A must hold, a contradiction. It therefore can never be the case that a polarizing candidate is neither first nor last in a system with unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives.
@MackJCM
@MackJCM 7 лет назад
In short, if a polarizing candidate were in the middle somewhere, you could take the winner and loser of the election, and make every voter rank the loser over the winner with no other changes. Then unanimity means the previous loser beats the previous winner, but independence means neither can cross the polarizing candidate's position, so one of our properties is violated.
@pandoradoggle
@pandoradoggle 7 лет назад
How does proportional representation figure into the problem?
@b43xoit
@b43xoit 5 лет назад
Voting for a single winner and for multiple winners are almost distinct topics. I'm not sure whether the Arrow theorem applies to the latter.
@GordonHugenay
@GordonHugenay 7 лет назад
I don't see why the challenge problem should be true: say one person votes A>B>C, and one person votes C>A>B, then C is a polarizing candidate, but what's wrong with the ranking A>C>B?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
Suppose that there are two voters, and they do in fact vote that way. A>B>C C>A>B And your method gives as a result A>C>B. Or in other words, A>B + A>C + C>B. But now let's suppose A and B swap places on both ballots. B>A>C C>B>A Now B is ahead of A on every ballot, so due to Unanimity it should be B>A But the relative rankings of A vs C and B vs C is the same, so by IIA it should remain A>C and C>B, but through transitivity that implies A>B, which contradicts Unanimity.
@GordonHugenay
@GordonHugenay 7 лет назад
thank you very much for the clarification (the definition of IIA is rather complicated), I think I can even see a proof of the claim now (it's basically just a slightly more generally phrased version of your comment): suppose for a contradiction that C is a polarizing candidate, but isn't placed first or last in the final ranking, i.e. there exists A, B such that A>C and C>B. now on every ballot with A>B, swap A and B such that B>A on every ballot. since C is a polarizing candidate, this is an irrelevant alternative with respect to C, so it must still hold A>C and C>B, but by unanimity B>A, which is a contradiction.
@feldar
@feldar 7 лет назад
Shouldn't the Condorcet Criterion be that if a candidate wins a head-to-head election with *every* other candidate they should be the overall winner? If it's any overall winner then everyone could vote A-B-C and the criterion would say that B should win because they beat C, even though A clearly beat both B and C.
@thejswaroop5230
@thejswaroop5230 2 года назад
All I understood is........ dictatorship is where one main ballot acts as a bottleneck of the whole election
@vikrantnayak5670
@vikrantnayak5670 4 года назад
Meanwhile , ARROW - what are you trying to teach ??
@christopherplant6178
@christopherplant6178 5 лет назад
This theorem is not merely a problem for democracy, but for _all_ human affairs with more than two possible outcomes: _nothing_ is immune; sports are particularly susceptible (round-robin or pair-wise comparison, brackets etc.); inheritance and succession are as well.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 5 лет назад
Arrow's theorem only applies to ranked-based systems. Rating-based systems evade it. 4:18 The theorem that is completely unevadeable is Gibbard's theorem (~"no method is strategyproof").
@thermotronica
@thermotronica 7 лет назад
Not trying to start something because i know you all worked hard, but around the 7 min point whats up with box lining the boxes together?? Its slightly off. Where the layers not in the same program? Its driving me bananas. But good vid overall. Rant over. Thanks. Good job
@firebrain2991
@firebrain2991 7 лет назад
Why is purple first in round three? Shouldn't it be last?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
Vote Test 3 is round 3 from earlier in the video. At the time, Kelsey supposed the mystery system said Purple was the winner in round 3, which means Purple was preferred to Green. Each of the modified ballots have the same relative rankings for Purple and Green. So, by IIA, Purple must be preferred to green with the modified ballots.
@kartikpatil5097
@kartikpatil5097 3 года назад
at 7:10 how does purple end up at the top of the rankings in round 3? Clearly, more people prefer blue to purple, red to blue and red to purple, green to red, green to blue and green to purple, so the order should be Green, Red, Blue, Purple?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 3 года назад
If the method was majoritarian, then yes green would be above purple. But we didn't assume majoritarianism, only Unanimity and IIA.
@radekhladik7895
@radekhladik7895 7 лет назад
Only -1000000 for punching in the face? I would expect -infinity on this channel...
@billyrobertson3170
@billyrobertson3170 7 лет назад
Challenge Problem Solution: (EDIT: When I originally wrote this, I accidentally assumed that all candidates are treated equally and I didn't notice, but luckily this is still provable using unanimity!) If we have an election with a polarizing candidate, consider all groups of two candidates where one of the candidates is polarizing. Every group of two will have exactly the same voting pattern, with each voter either preferring the polarizing candidate or not preferring them. So however our voting procedure decides a relative ranking between the polarizing candidate and another candidate, (assuming all candidates are treated equally, [1]) the relative ranking will be the same regardless of the other candidate. This means that the procedure prefers the polarizing candidate to every other candidate or prefers every other candidate more than the polarizing candidate. So by of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, the polarizing candidate will come in either first or last place. Q.E.D. References: [1] David de Kloet, "I can prove your extra assumption using unanimity", Reply to Cantor's Cat's Solution, 24 June 2017.
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
There's no (axiomatic) reason why the voting system would treat all candidates equally!
@billyrobertson3170
@billyrobertson3170 7 лет назад
Crap - Thanks for pointing that out!
@TheManxLoiner
@TheManxLoiner 7 лет назад
I like the reference!
@jelleverest
@jelleverest 6 лет назад
At 7:29, I don't know why purple wins round three, because overall, green is ranked higher than purple, thus it cannot be first, right?
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 6 лет назад
I think it's showing that even a truly bizarre method that doesn't meet our normal conceptions of a voting method (like majoritarianism) cannot wiggle it's way out of this theorem as long as it passes IIA and Unanimity (and is ranked).
@jelleverest
@jelleverest 6 лет назад
Skyval Ream oh yeah that could be it, thanks!
@TheTruthSentMe
@TheTruthSentMe 7 лет назад
I missed the point about what differentiated voter 2 from the others. What made him the dictator? I guess there must be certain circumstances for that to happen.
@MustSeto
@MustSeto 7 лет назад
What made him the dictator is that the "mystery method" gave those particular results at 7:14. If a method passes Unanimity and IIA, and it gives those results, voters 2 must have been a dictator from the beginning.
Далее
Is Democracy Impossible? (Arrow's Theorem)
10:15
Просмотров 99 тыс.
Cute
00:16
Просмотров 3,7 млн
ДОКАЗАЛ ЧТО НЕ КАБЛУК #shorts
00:30
The Devil's Staircase | Infinite Series
13:34
Просмотров 266 тыс.
International Math Olympiad | 2005 Q4
7:45
Просмотров 49 тыс.
The flaw in every voting system
18:26
Просмотров 421 тыс.
Arrow's Impossibility Theorem Explained
9:16
Просмотров 23 тыс.
The Mathematical Danger of Democratic Voting
8:14